John Stuart Mill’s Concept of Liberty


John Stuart Mill (20 May 1806 – 8 May 1873), British philosopher, political economist, civil servant and Member of Parliament, was an influential liberal thinker of the 19th century. His On Liberty contains a rational justification of the freedom of the individual in opposition to the claims of the state to impose unlimited control, and has become a classic of libertarian philosophy.

Mill’s subject of this Essay is not the so-called Liberty of the Will, but “Civil, or Social Liberty: the nature and limits of the power which can be legitimately exercised by society over the individual”. 
               
Mill draws our attention to historical overview of  the  “struggle between authority and liberty” describing the tyranny of government, which may prove a “dangerous weapon” and which, in his view, needs to be controlled by the liberty of the citizens. He divides this control of authority into two mechanisms: necessary “political liberties or rights”, belonging to citizens, and the “establishment of constitutional checks”.

Mill suggests that mankind became happy to be ruled “by a master” or by monarchy, if his rule would be guaranteed against tyranny. However, mankind soon developed into democracy where “there was no fear of tyrannizing over self”. “This may seem axiomatic”, he says, but “the people who exercise the power are not always the same people with those over whom it is exercised”. As a result, there may happen, in Mill’s terms, the “tyranny of the majority (a phrase Mill takes from Tocqueville). 

As a consequence, the tyranny of the majority is worse than tyranny of government: One can be protected from a tyrant, but it is harder to be protected “against the tyranny of the prevailing opinion and feeling”. [People will be compelled to follow the rules made by the prevailing majority opinion, though it may not be correct and will be fashioned by it.] Thus there can be no safeguard in law against the tyranny of the majority

One argument that Mill develops, in his concept of liberty, further than any previous philosopher is the harm principle. The harm principle holds that each individual has the right to act as he wants, so long as these actions do not harm others. Mill declares the individual freedom:
“Over himself, over his own body and mind, the individual is sovereign.”
According to Mill, there is only one legitimate reason for the exercise of power over individuals:
“That the only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilised community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others.”

However, Mill excuses those who are “incapable of self-government” from this principle, such as young children or those living in “backward states of society”. Because, they do not, and cannot, have sovereignty over self. Moreover, Mill also includes “barbarians”, considered as “non-age”, as they cannot be sovereign over self.

Mill, unlike other liberal theorists, makes no appeal to “abstract right” in order to justify the harm principle. Mill argues that abiding by the harm principle is desirable because it promotes what he calls the “free development of individuality” or the development of our humanity.
A basic philosophical problem presented by Mill’s concept of liberty is what counts as “harm to others.” Where should we mark the boundary between conduct that is principally self-regarding versus conduct that involves others? Does drug-use cause harm to others sufficient to be prevented? Does prostitution? Pornography? Should polygamy be allowed? How about public nudity? Though these are difficult questions, Mill provides the reader with a principled way of deliberating about them.
                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                       Mill now states some components or manifestations of his anti-paternalistic principle of human liberty:
*the freedom to express opinions,
* the freedom to pursue tastes and pursuits as long as they do not cause harm,
* the “freedom to unite” or the freedom of assembly.
“No society [...or...] none”, in Mill's view, “is completely free in which they [these freedoms] do not exist absulute and unqualified.”

            Mill defends the liberty of free speech, even if it is false: he holds that free discourse is a necessary condition for intellectual and social progress. Because, first, open exchange of ideas helps individuals abandon erroneous beliefs. Second, these beliefs are kept from declining into mere dogma, by forcing other individuals to re-examine and re-affirm their beliefs in the process of debate.

Utiliterian approach is another concern of Mill’s concept of liberty. James A Stegenga (1973) says “he is usually included among those writers who followed Jeremy Bentham and James Mill, J. S. Mill's father, in maintaining that the principle of utility does and should govern all human actions.” It is important to note, however, that Mill makes it clear throughout On Liberty that he “regard[s] utility as the ultimate appeal on all ethical questions.” To Mill, “actions are right in proportion as they tend to promote happiness; wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness” (Collected Works, X.210).


Individual liberty is also reflected in John Stuart Mill’s religious view, influenced by John Locke. He holds that individuals are rational enough to make decisions about their good being and choose any religion they want to.

In order to draw conclusion, we must assert that John Stuart Mill has fullfilled the demand of time with his essay On Liberty. It has become an enormously influential work; the concept of  liberty presented within it remains the basis of much political thought since. Even , “to this day, a copy of On Liberty has been passed to the president of the British Liberals and then Liberal Democrats as a symbol of office and succession from the party that Mill helped found.” (Wikipedia). However, On Liberty can be criticised for being overly vague on the limits of liberty and for placing too much emphasis on the rights of the individual. It can further be suggested that it does not make a useful distinction between actions that only harm oneself and actions that harm others. Yet, bearing these criticisms in mind, On Liberty does provide an impassioned plea for tolerance and a necessary recognition that it is not possible to be completely sure that any particular way is the best way to live.


Works Cited:
Cowling, Maurice. Mill and Liberalism. Cambridge, 1963.
Mill, John Stuart. The Collected Works of John Stuart Mill. Gen. Ed. John M. Robson. 33 vols. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1963-91.
Stegenga, James A , J. S. Mill's concept of liberty and the principle of utility, The Journal of Value Inquiry 7, Springer Netherlands, 1973.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Postcolonial Study of Heart of Darkness

The character of Helen in The Iliad

Search for Identity in A House For Mr. Biswas